Whether or not they’re well-educated enough to know the
phrase “moral relativism,” there are a lot of people—the fervently religious in
particular—who are absolutely terrified of the concept. Supposedly, if there’s
not some objectively right morality (usually, but not always, dictated by some
kind of god), then there’s no way of condemning the Holocaust, rape, or
whatever else the opponent of moral relativism can come up with. This argument
is particularly popular by religious fundamentalists as a supposed criticism of
atheism. In reality, there are quite a few atheists who believe in objective
morality (Sam Harris, for instance)—but, really, regardless of religiosity, I think moral relativism is not
something to be wary of, but something to embrace, and stand up for.
Moral relativism, in my view, is the idea that everyone is
free to decide on their own set of moral rules. What are considered fundamental
values differs radically from person to person, and so it only makes sense that
each person should be at liberty to decide what sort of moral rules logically
follow from their personal values. Without this principle, the idea of being an
individual or “choosing your own path” becomes meaningless. Objective morality
is the demand that each person adhere to a certain set of rules, and it grants
no right to challenge those rules. Moral relativism, on the other hand, offers
everyone the opportunity to reflect on what they stand for and devise their own
rules and guidelines from those principles.
As for the objections to moral relativism, a close
examination proves them to be completely without merit. Most people, I think,
can agree that there’s no objective code for what makes a good movie or good
book—sure, there are guidelines, but they aren’t rigid or unquestionable. Even
those guidelines weren’t handed down by God; they were just arrived at by a
sort of general consensus. But that doesn’t mean that there’s no way to
criticize 50 Shades of Gray or Troll 2—the fact that there’s no objective
definition of a “good movie” or “good book” doesn’t mean I have to accept these
works as good, or even that I can’t view them as bad. Whether a movie or a book
is good or bad in my opinion depends on my own personal taste, and my personal beliefs
on what makes a movie or book good or bad. The same concept applies with moral
relativism; there’s no objective right or wrong, but that doesn’t mean you
can’t condemn actions if you find them to be abhorrent. Furthermore, no one
needs some abstract moral code to oppose mass murder, or rape, or torture; they
just need some amount of interest in the well-being of others. To imply it’s
impossible to care about other people’s welfare without being commanded to do
so by some set of divine rules is downright insulting to any concept of human
decency.
I suppose the great fear here is that if everyone is allowed
to base their morality on their feelings rather than some kind of
unquestionable maxims, then we’ll have a societal breakdown as everyone acts on
whatever whim they have at the moment. Ultimately, that idea is just kind of
silly. In fact, moral relativism affords us a great opportunity as a society:
to actually evaluate whether the values we teach our children and (theoretically)
abide by ourselves are actually effective at maintaining a happy and stable
society, or whether they’re outdated and should be done away with. For
instance, the only reason some of our more prudish sexual mores have hung
around so long is probably just because society shuns anyone who tries to
question them, rather than actually listening to their arguments. Moral
relativism doesn’t dictate that our society can’t hold to any values, but
rather that the values it does hold to should be thought out properly instead
of being clung to out of some blind faith in their veracity.
In rebuttal to those who try to argue that moral relativism
is dangerous and enables the worst and most damaging behaviors, I’d like to
argue the exact opposite: moral absolutism
is what’s truly dangerous and what often justifies the worst things in history.
For instance, it’s a common narrative that Hitler’s rise was due to moral
relativism, but the exact opposite is true: some of the groups Hitler
targeted—homosexuals, for instance—were chosen out of some twisted idea of
protecting public morality. At least, that’s how he and his cronies portrayed it, and that’s why the German population went along with it.
The danger of moral absolutism is that when you’re convinced
you’re enforcing some morality that can’t be challenged, it’s easy to justify
the worst atrocities, because anyone who stands in the way of your moral
crusade is immoral ipso facto, and
therefore whatever happens to them is well-deserved. Moral relativism doesn’t
have this issue; no principle or value is above criticism, and you have to
evaluate your actions by their actual effects, not whether they’re promoting
some sacred cause. For a moral absolutist, it’s easy to explain why they and
their followers can commit heinous crimes and not be just as bad (or worse) than
those they oppose: “We’re the ones fighting for what’s right.” It’s the same
attitude Bob Dylan described when he sang, “you never ask questions when God’s
on your side.” For a moral relativist, though, the question is quite a bit more
difficult, because they recognize that if they’re harming others as much, or
more, than those they’re fighting against, there may be no rational way to
claim some moral high-ground.
Lastly, I’d like to argue something that might seem
counterintuitive to many people: moral relativism, at least in the practical
sense, is not at all incompatible with religion. For instance, one can look at
the philosophy of the devout Christian Søren Kierkegaard. In Kierkegaard’s view, ethics are just rules set
up for the benefit of society, but it’s ultimately up to each individual to
decide their own morals, based on who they are. Kierkegaard believed that the
only legitimate relationship with God was an intensely personal one that
superseded any human institutions, such as churches, for instance. And,
Kierkegaard believed, what’s right from a religious or teleological perspective
(which was up to each person to divine from their relationship with God)
sometimes runs completely contrary to all of the ethical rules society holds
dear. This is, for all intents and purposes, a belief in moral relativism.
Ultimately, the choice is clear: if we value the idea that
each person should be able to be true to themselves, to choose their own
way—that is, if we actually believe all the clichés we have about “being
yourself”—moral relativism is the only rationally consistent choice. If we
believe the chief virtue a person can have is an unwavering obedience to
rules—necessarily, the rules of man (who wrote all those holy books, after
all?)—then moral absolutism is the appropriate position to take. It’s a choice
for each person to make, but I thought I’d do my best to dispel any illusions
about the options.
No comments:
Post a Comment